1 Introduction

In a landmark decision in May 2020, the General Court of the European Union annulled the decision of the European Commission to block the acquisition of Telefonica UK by Hutchison 3G UK: The Court stated that the Commission failed to prove that this acquisition would have harmed competition.Footnote 1 This case highlights the policy relevance of the question how antitrust agencies produce evidence, and how the incentives to produce evidence in merger control can be enhanced.

We analyze evidence production in merger control as a delegation problem in an inquisitorial competition system. Depending on its ex-ante uncertain efficiency type, a merger proposal can be anti- or pro-competitive: consumer welfare reducing or increasing. A principal-agent problem between the legislator—whose objective is to maximize consumer welfare—and the antitrust agency—whose objective is consumer surplus minus effort costs—arises from the fact that the agency’s investigative effort in a merger case is non-contractible.

We investigate how different action sets of the agency affect its incentives to exert effort and acquire information on the efficiency type of a proposed merger. We compare the case (1) in which the agency can either approve or prohibit the merger altogether with the case (2) where a merger can also be cleared conditionally on the basis of a remedy solution. Throughout our analysis we take the remedy solution as a compromising choice that is optimal from an ex ante perspective: whenever only the a priori information on the merger’s efficiency type is available.

Our main contribution is to show that allowing for remedial solutions deteriorates incentives for the agency. As the remedy solution represents a compromising choice and thereby the negative effect of a false extreme decision, allowing for it reduces the agency’s incentives to obtain information on the merger’s efficiency type. Altogether, the availability of the remedy solution reduces the agency’s effort provision when compared to a no-remedy regime that forces the agency to either to approve or to prohibit the merger.

In contrast, in a scenario in which only extreme options are implementable, a false decision bears the risk of making a wrong decision with strong negative consequences. Therefore, in the absence of the remedy solution, the agency acquires more information in order to avoid such negative consequences. Thus, it can be desirable overall for the legislator to remove the remedy solution from the agency’s choice set.Footnote 2

Finally, we analyze “evidence-based remedies” whereby a remedy solution can be implemented only if the agency has gathered and evaluated information that supports the ex-post optimality of the remedy decision. This leads to higher information (and higher consumer welfare) levels than in the case where remedies cannot be implemented. As a consequence, requiring evidence for the remedial solution is always weakly preferred over a no-remedy regime.

2 The Model

The model that we present in the following builds on two models that have been proposed in the literature: Cosnita-Langlais and Tropeano (2012), and Szalay (2005). First, our merger model follows the reduced-form model proposed by Cosnita-Langlais and Tropeano (2012), whereby different merger types can be uniquely characterized by an efficiency parameter. This efficiency parameter represents the net effect of the usual trade-off that goes along with a merger: On the one hand, we assume that the merger has the potential—if not counteracted by efficiencies and/or a remedy—to yield market power for the post-merger firm, which generates an upward pricing pressure. On the other hand, a merger may decrease production costs, which generates a downward price pressure. Mergers differ in the efficiencies that they generate (see Besanko and Spulber 1993), and the higher is the efficiency, the stronger is the second effect relative to the first one; and the more desirable is a merger from a consumer-surplus point of view.

To learn about a merger’s efficiency type, the antitrust agency has to invest effort.Footnote 3 To model the principal-agent problem between the legislator and the antitrust agency as well as the agency’s information acquisition problem, we employ the quite general model by Szalay (2005), who examines a principal-agent model in which the agent collects information and then chooses a verifiable action. The agent’s effort is not contractible and the principal cannot design an incentive compatible con tract based on ex post outcomes. The critical step in this analysis is to focus on the agent’s incentives as a result of the composition of her choice set. It is shown that it can be optimal to remove the intermediate choices from the agent’s action set to increase her incentives to acquire information. The model that we present in the following basically applies the model by Szalay (2005) to antitrust.

We now formally introduce our model: In our inquisitorial system, the legislator delegates the enforcement of merger control (evidence production and the final decision making) to an agency.Footnote 4 Their objectives are aligned in the following sense. The objective of the agency is consumer welfare, but the agency also takes its effort costs for information acquisition into account and therefore maximizes consumer surplus minus its information costs.Footnote 5

Mergers differ in the efficiencies, e, that they generate. The distribution of efficiencies is given by the density function f(e) on the interval \(e\in [\underline{e},\overline{e}]\), where \(\underline{e}\) denotes the lowest and \(\overline{e}\) the highest possible efficiency level. The prior distribution of efficiencies is common knowledge, while the specific efficiency level of a particular merger is the private information of the merging firms. The agency can acquire information on a merger’s efficiency level by exerting costly effort to observe the true efficiency type with probability \(\beta \in [0,1]\). If the agency chooses a particular value \(\beta\), it learns the true efficiency type with probability \(\beta\) and does not obtain any information on the merger type with counter probability \(1-\beta\).Footnote 6 In case the merger type is not known, the agency will use the distribution of efficiencies (namely, f(e)) to determine the ex-ante optimal action, and will implement this.

Costs for information acquisition are given by \(C(\beta )\), which fulfills the Inada conditions \(C(0)=0\), \(C^{\prime }(\beta )>0\), \(C^{\prime \prime }(\beta )>0\), \(\lim _{\beta \rightarrow 1}C(\beta )=+\infty\). The Inada conditions guarantee us an inner solution to the information-acquisition problem of the agency.

We investigate the agency’s choices of \(\beta\) under two regimes: NR (no-remedy regime) and R (remedy regime). Under NR, the agency can only approve or prohibit the merger altogether. Under regime R, the agency can also condition its approval on a remedy solution. We assume that a unique remedy exists for every merger proposal, and that the implementation of this remedy does not render a proposed merger unprofitable for the proposing firms.Footnote 7

Let X indicate the agency’s merger decision, \(X\in \{M,N,R\}\), which can be: an approval (\(X=M\)); a prohibition (\(X=N\)); or an approval conditional on a remedy (\(X=R\)). Given a merger of a certain efficiency type e, let \(W^{X}(e)\) denote the change in consumer welfare when the agency adopts decision X. The expected change of consumer welfare if decision X is adopted is given by \(\overline{W}^{X}=\int _{\underline{e}}^{\overline{e} }W^{X}(e)f(e)de\). If a merger proposal is prohibited, consumer welfare does not change, so that \(\overline{W}^{N}=0\) holds.

We impose the following assumptions on the pre- and the post-merger market outcomes, which are in line with models that analyze structural remedies in oligopolistic markets such as Cabral (2003), Vergé (2010), Vasconcelos (2010), and Dertwinkel-Kalt and Wey (2016):

A1: Consumer welfare \(W^{X}(e)\) is continuous and strictly monotonically increasing in e for all \(X\in \{M,R\}\). Let \(W^{M}(\underline{e})<0\) and \(W^{M}( \overline{e})>0\). Furthermore, assume that

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\mathrm {d}W^{M}(e)}{\mathrm {d}e}>\frac{\mathrm {d}W^{R}(e)}{\mathrm {d}e} >0\text {.} \end{aligned}$$
(1)

Condition (1) is intuitive: The (positive or negative) effect of a merger’s efficiency affects consumer welfare to a larger degree if the merger is fully implemented than if its effects are mitigated by the remedy solution. This setting is illustrated in Fig. 1.

From Assumption A1 it follows that the function \(W^{M}(e)\) has at most one zero. \(W^{R}(e)\) has also at most one zero and intersects with \(W^{M}(e)\) at most once. Without loss of generality, we assume that all three points of intersection exist,Footnote 8 and are denoted by \(e^{\prime }\) (such that \(W^{R}(e)=0\)), \(e^{\prime \prime }\) (such that \(W^{R}(e)=W^{M}(e)\)) and \(\hat{e}\) (such that \(W^{M}(e)=0\)), respectively. Let \(e_{1}:=\min \{e^{\prime },\hat{e}\}\) and \(e_{2}:=\max \{e^{\prime \prime },\hat{e}\}\). For brevity, we assume that there is zero probability mass on the threshold values \(e^{\prime }\), \(e^{\prime \prime }\) and \(\hat{e}\).

From a consumer welfare perspective: A prohibition of the merger is optimal for \(\underline{e}<e<e_{1}\); remedies are optimal for \(e_{1}<e<e_{2}\); and a full merger is optimal for \(e_{2}<e<\overline{e}\). Note that these intervals may be empty, for instance, if \(e_{2}<e_{1}\).

Fig. 1
figure 1

Thresholds concerning W for a continuous distribution of merger efficiencies

A2: Ex ante—based on the distribution of efficiencies—an approval conditional on a remedy is preferred from a consumer welfare perspective: \(\overline{W}^{R}>\max \{ \overline{W}^{M},0\}\).

According to A2, we invoke a “remedy-favoring assumption”: Ex ante—before the acquisition of costly evidence—it is optimal to approve any merger proposal that is conditional on a remedy. This mirrors our motivation to interpret the decision to approve a merger that is conditional on remedies as an intermediate option which is optimal if no information is available (as in Szalay 2005). In contrast, extreme decisions such as an unconditional approval or the outright prohibition of the merger bear the risk of making a “large” mistake with substantial consumer welfare losses. Hence, in the absence of any additional information, the remedy option represents a relatively “safe” choice

We distinguish between two types of remedy regimes: First, we analyze the “standard” remedy regime as described above; and second we examine “evidence-based” remedies. In the former case, a remedial solution can be implemented without any empirical justification, so that its use will be decided only in terms of expected values. In the latter case, a remedial solution can be implemented only when there is hard evidence that the remedy is indeed optimal; that is, information must be gathered and evaluated that supports the optimality of the remedy decision.

3 Analysis

3.1 Standard Remedy Regime

We analyze the following game: In stage zero, a merger is proposed.Footnote 9 In the first stage, the legislator decides on the agency’s action space: The legislator decides whether remedies are feasible (regime R) or not (regime NR). In the second stage, the agency decides on the quality of information \(\beta\) it acquires. Finally, in the third stage, the agency makes its final judgment on the merger proposal. If it has not learned the precise efficiency type (which happens with probability \(1-\beta\)), it decides on what is feasible and ex-ante optimal.

We solve this game via backward induction: The agency’s decision in the third stage depends on the availability of the remedial option and the information \(\beta\) that it has acquired in the second stage. Suppose regime R applies: If the agency holds information on the merger’s type, then it decides according to the following decision rule: A merger of type \(e\in [e_{2},\overline{e}]\) is approved; a merger of type \(e\in [e_{1},e_{2}]\) is approved with a remedy; and a merger of type \(e\in [\underline{e},e_{1}]\) is prohibited. Thus, with information on the efficiency of the merger at hand, the agency always implements the (ex post) consumer welfare-maximizing solution. If, to the contrary, the agency does not hold any information, then the remedy is implemented due to our remedy-favoring assumption A2.

Next, suppose regime NR applies: Thus, if no information is held, then the merger is prohibited if \(\max \{0,\overline{W}^{M}\}=0\); and it is approved if \(\max \{0,\overline{W}^{M}\}=\overline{W}^{M}\). If information is held, a merger of type \(e\in [\hat{e},\overline{e}]\) is fully approved; and a merger of type \(e\in [\underline{e},\hat{e}]\) is prohibited.

In the second stage, the agency chooses the level of information \(\beta \in [0,1]\). Under regime R, the equilibrium level of information acquisition \(\beta _{R}\) is given by the maximization of

$$\begin{aligned}&\beta \left( \int _{\underline{e}}^{e_1}f(e)W^{N}(e)de+ \int _{e_{1}}^{e_{2}}f(e)W^{R}(e)de+\int _{e_{2}}^{\overline{e} }f(e)W^{M}(e)de\right) \nonumber \\&\quad +\,(1-\beta )\overline{W}^{R}-C(\beta ) \text {.} \end{aligned}$$
(2)

Under regime NR, the equilibrium is given by the maximization of

$$\begin{aligned} \beta \left( \int _{\underline{e}}^{\hat{e}}f(e)W^{N}(e)de+\int _{\hat{e}}^{ \overline{e}}f(e)W^{M}(e)de\right) +(1-\beta )\max \{0,\overline{W} ^{M}\}-C(\beta )\text {.} \end{aligned}$$
(3)

With \(W^{N}(e)=0\) the optimal information levels \(\beta _{ NR }^{*}\) and \(\beta _{R}^{*}\) follow from the first-order conditions

$$\begin{aligned}&\int _{e_{1}}^{e_{2}}f(e)W^{R}(e)de+\int _{e_{2}}^{\overline{e} }f(e)W^{M}(e)de-\overline{W}^{R}\overset{!}{=}C^{\prime }(\beta _{R}^{*}) \text {, and } \end{aligned}$$
(4)
$$\begin{aligned}&\int _{\hat{e}}^{\overline{e}}f(e)W^{M}(e)de-\max \{0,\overline{W}^{M}\} \overset{!}{=}C^{\prime }(\beta _{ NR }^{*})\text {, } \end{aligned}$$
(5)

respectively.

To focus our analysis on the agency’s effort choice, we now maintain the assumption that the remedial option is never the ex post optimal choice.

A3: Ex post the remedial option is never optimal: \(e_1=e_2=\hat{e}\).

We then obtain the following proposition.

Proposition 1

Under Assumption A3, the agency acquires a higher information level under regime NR than under regime R . Expected consumer surplus is higher under NR if and only if the higher level of information is sufficient to counterbalance the detrimental effects of the remedy’s removal in the no-information scenario: if

$$\begin{aligned}&\underbrace{(\beta _{ NR }^{*}-\beta _{R}^{*})\cdot \int _{ \hat{e}}^{\overline{e}}f(e)W^{M}(e)de}_{\text {positive effect of } \textit{NR} \text { due to more information}}\nonumber \\&\qquad >\underbrace{(1-\beta _{R}^{*})\cdot \overline{ W}^{R}-(1-\beta _{ NR }^{*})\cdot \max \{ \overline{W}^{M},0\}}_{ \text {negative effect of }{} \textit{NR} \text { when no information available}} \text {.} \end{aligned}$$
(6)

Proof

Comparing (4) and (5) under A3 immediately yields that \(\beta _{ NR }^{*}>\beta _{ R }^{*}\). Formula (6) follows from rearranging (2) and (3). \(\square\)

If remedies are not ex post optimal for any merger proposal, then the removal of the intermediate option increases the agency’s incentives to acquire information. This result is driven by the following intuition: If remedies are feasible, it may be optimal for the agency to exert very little effort and to apply remedies since the potential error that accompanies this decision is limited. If, however, remedies are not feasible, then the potential error that is associated with an extreme decision might be so high that exerting more effort—acquiring better information—is optimal for the agency. With better information at hand, the agency limits the potentially high costs that are associated with an erroneous decision.

Besides this positive incentive effect of a removal of the remedy option, the removal also creates a real cost because the remedy is optimal on average: in the absence of concrete information with respect to a proposal’s type. By acquiring more information, remedies become less important since the range where they are optimal—the number of no-information scenarios—shrinks.

Whether or not the additionally acquired information also gives rise to an increase in consumer surplus depends on the interplay between consumer welfare losses that are due to the removal of remedies and the gains in consumer welfare due to the higher information acquisition level. In equilibrium, the positive surplus effect of an improved information level may overcompensate the welfare losses that result from the removal of the remedial option. In that case, the legislator optimally decides to remove the remedy option from the agency’s action space.

The optimality of the extreme option regime NR depends on the exact shape of the information cost function C. Regime NR is most likely to dominate regime R from a consumer perspective if the difference in information acquisition is sufficiently high between the regimes—which is the case if information acquisitions costs are at an intermediate level: C is neither too steep nor too flat. Then, to spur the information acquisition incentives of the agency and thereby to increase consumer welfare, the legislator finds the removal of the remedial option attractive.

Note that Proposition 1 holds qualitatively not only when remedies are not ex post optimal, but also if the range where remedies are ex post optimal is not too large.

That an inquisitorial law enforcement system has insufficient incentives to produce evidence has been also shown in other setups: In Dewatripont and Tirole (1999) the inquisitorial system decides too often for an extreme option which is in stark contrast to our model. That difference is due to their key assumption that the obtained information can be conflicting. The inquisitorial authority has insufficient incentives to gather a second piece of information that might stand in conflict with the initially obtained information. In our setup, in contrast, the agency already has too few incentives to obtain the very first piece of information with the relatively safe, intermediate option at hand.

3.2 Remedies with “Hard Evidence”

We now suppose that the legislator can opt for a third regime—in addition to approval/denial—in which the remedy option can be implemented only when the agency has obtained evidence as to the remedy’s optimality. Let us denote this third regime by \(R^{S}\): In this case, a remedy cannot be applied if no information on the exact merger type has been acquired, so that it cannot be used as an intermediate option. Rather, the agency must gather information and persuasively argue that the remedial solution is indeed optimal if it wants to implement it.Footnote 10

While under regime NR the agency chooses \(\beta _{ NR }\) in order to maximize Condition (3), under regime \(R^{S}\) it chooses \(\beta _{R^{S}}\) in order to maximize

$$\begin{aligned}&\beta \left( \int _{\underline{e}}^{e_{1}}f(e)W^{N}(e)de+ \int _{e_{1}}^{e_{2}}f(e)W^{R}(e)de+\int _{e_{2}}^{\overline{e} }f(e)W^{M}(e)de\right) \nonumber \\&+(1-\beta )\max \{0,\overline{W}^{M}\}- C(\beta )\text {.} \end{aligned}$$
(7)

Note that the equilibrium information level according to (7) is always weakly higher under the evidence-based remedy regime than under a no-remedy regime: \(\beta _{R^{S}}^{*}\ge \beta _{ NR }^{*}\) holds, as information becomes more valuable. In fact, should the agency discover that the remedy is the optimal option, it can implement it under regime \(R^{S}\) while it has to implement only a second-best option under regime NR. Consequently, the evidence-based remedy regime always induces both a weakly higher information level and a weakly higher consumer welfare level than under NR .

Corollary 1

If the legislator prefers regime NR over regime R, it prefers regime \(R^{S}\) over regimes R and NR.

The evidence-based remedy regime is appealing to the legislator for the following reasons: While this regime allows the implementation of the remedy if this represents the best available option, the regime eliminates the effort-frustrating effect of a remedy as a relatively safe intermediate option. Therefore, this regime always outperforms a no-remedy regime. Note that this point is not obvious: \(R^{S}\) still has the disadvantage that it does not allow for the ex ante optimal option—the remedy—if no information is available. As we have shown, however, it can be optimal to remove the ex-ante optimal option in order to provide better incentives to the agency. If regime NR outperforms regime R, then \(R^{S}\) is the preferred regime of the legislator.

4 Conclusion

An inquisitorial enforcement system that allows for a remedial clearing of a merger is likely to suffer from an incentive problem as the agency’s incentives to exert effort into information gathering and processing can be reduced by the intermediate option. The intermediate decision serves as a “safe” option that avoids the risks that are associated with extreme rulings; consequently, an extreme-option system may lead to greater evidence acquisition incentives and thus possibly higher consumer welfare. While this insight appears to be a simple one, it stands in contrast to the generally optimistic view on merger remedies as, for instance, expressed in the European legislation, which describes remedies as an effective way to restore competition (EC 2008, Article 22).

We thereby complement recent empirical studies that have taken a critical stance on remedies; these studies find that remedies have often failed to restore effective competition (Davies and Olczak 2010; Duso et al. 2011, 2013, Kwoka and Moss 2012, and Kwoka 2013, 2015, 2019).Footnote 11 Complementary to this direct effect of failing to effectively restore competition, our analysis delineates a novel indirect effect that merger remedies could have: They could reduce the incentives of the antitrust agencies to invest in evidence production. Ultimately, this incentive effect could be so strong that an overall ban of the remedial option—a “no-remedy” regime—improves merger control and consumer welfare. Notably, Kwoka (2020) concludes his extensive studies on the effectiveness of merger remedies with a similar statement (see our introductory quotation).

Finally, we have shown that merger control should unambiguously improve even beyond the “no-remedy” regime when a remedy solution is based on hard evidence that supports its optimality. Again, this finding is mirrored in the observation that remedy regulations have been tightened over time in the EU; in particular, the informational burden for remedies has been raised which is reflected in the publication of the “Revised Notice on Remedies” (see EC 2008, and Lindsay and Berridge 2012: 617).

Our model can be also interpreted in a different way, where information collection regards the merging firms’ potential to exercise market power. On the one end are firms that operate in different relevant markets. In this case, a merger would correspond to a highly efficient merger in the current setup, which is unambiguously positive from a consumer perspective. On the other end are firms that operate in the very same relevant market. This case would correspond to the lowly-efficient merger in the current setup, that is unambiguously bad from a consumer perspective. Partly overlapping relevant markets would correspond to the case of intermediate efficiencies. Thus, our model could be re-interpreted for the case where the agency does not acquire information on efficiencies, but on the degree to which relevant markets overlap or market power can be exercised.

Our analysis best applies when there is a unique remedy candidate, as in the case where a certain branch is to be divested off or not. In fact, however, it could take serious effort to determine what a good remedy could be. When this is the case, the effects we delineate are compromised. A model incorporating effort to find a good remedy would include an additional stage in which the agency invests effort to find a suitable remedy, and the agency either has a fixed budget to allocate across these two tasks, or it faces costs that are increasing in both tasks. Our effects of excessive remedy implementation would only survive in case finding the suitable remedy is not too costly.

Our model has also abstracted from the endogeneity of projects that are chosen for in-depth investigation and the associated problem of endogenous (opportunity) costs of effort within the authority. Considering the interplay between project choices and informational effort from a delegation perspective is an interesting venue for further research.